La vuelta de las potencias en biología evolucionistahacia una ontología de lo posible

  1. Nuño de la Rosa, Laura 1
  1. 1 IAS-Research Institute, Donostia-San Sebastián, España
Revista:
Ludus vitalis: revista de filosofía de las ciencias de la vida = journal of philosophy of life sciences = revue de philosophie des sciences de la vie

ISSN: 1133-5165

Año de publicación: 2016

Volumen: 24

Número: 46

Páginas: 1-18

Tipo: Artículo

Otras publicaciones en: Ludus vitalis: revista de filosofía de las ciencias de la vida = journal of philosophy of life sciences = revue de philosophie des sciences de la vie

Resumen

The return of potencies in evolutionary biology: towards an ontology of what is possibleWhereas the Modern Synthesis view of evolution has been grounded on the theoretical pillars of molecular chance and historical contingency, the randomness of evolutionary change has been challenged from a phenomenological and an explanatory perspective. The investigation of the tempo and mode of evolution has entailed an increasing interest in the directionality of evolutionary change and the logics of morphospace. From a causal perspective, evodevo has brought to evolutionary biology many dispositional terms that highlight the ‘inherency’ (vs. the Darwinian contingency) of evolution. In this paper, I explore how the introduction of dispositions into the causal structure of evolutionary biology has lead evo-devo practitioners to confront the ontology of chance and contingency underlying the inherited view of evolution, and begin to articulate a dispositional theory of evolutionary change. Firstly, I analyze how the dialectics between the actual and the possible underlies many theoretical tensions between the population and developmental approaches to evolution. In this context, I distinguish two notions of the possible associated to different epistemological goals in evo-devo: the morphologically possible (variability) and the functionally possible (evolvability). Secondly, I explore how the introduction of the possible transforms the relationship between chance, determinism and contingency in evolutionary theory.

Referencias bibliográficas

  • Ahouse, J. C. (1998), “The tragedy of a priori selectionism: Dennett and Gould on adaptationism,” Biology and Philosophy 13 (3): 359-91. doi:10.1023/A:1006508719300.
  • Alberch, P. (1981), “Convergence and parallelism in foot morphology in the neotropical salamander genus Bolitoglossa. I. Function,” Evolution 12: 84-100.
  • — (1989), “The logic of monsters: evidence for internal constraint in development and evolution,” Geobios 12: 21-57.
  • Amundson, R. (1994), “Two concepts of constraint: Adaptationism and the challenge from developmental biology,” Philosophy of Science, 61 (4): 556-78.
  • — (2005), The Changing Role of the Embryo in Evolutionary Thought: Roots of Evo-Devo. Cambridge University Press.
  • Arthur, W. (2000), “The concept of developmental reprogramming and the quest for an inclusive theory of evolutionary mechanisms,” Evolution & Development 2 (1): 49-57.
  • Arthur, W., y M. Farrow (1999), “The pattern of variation in centipede segment number as an example of developmental constraint in evolution,” Journal of Theoretical Biology 200 (2): 183-91.
  • Brigandt, I. (2013a), “Evolutionary developmental biology and the limits of philosophical accounts of mechanistic explanation,” en Explanation in Biology, P.A. Braillard (ed.), Berlin: Springer.
  • — (2013b), “From developmental constraint to evolvability,” en Conceptual Change in Biology, editado por A. C. Love.
  • Brown, Rachael L (2014), “What evolvability really is,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 65 (3): 549-72. doi:10.1093/bjps/axt014.
  • Dawkins, R. (1989), “The evolution of evolvability,” Artificial Life 6: 201-20.
  • De Visser, J. A. G. M., J. Hermisson, G. P. Wagner, L. A. Meyers, Homayoun Bagheri-Chaichian, Jeffrey L. Blanchard, L. Chao, J. M. Cheverud, S. F. Elena, y W. Fontana (2003), “Perspective: evolution and detection of genetic robustness,” Evolution 57 (9): 1959 8211/unicode1972.
  • Dennett, D. C. (1995), Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life New York: Simon & Schuster.
  • Duboule, D. (2010), “The evo-devo comet,” EMBO Reports 11 (7): 489-489.
  • Eble, G. J. (2000), “Theoretical morphology: state of the art,” Paleobiology 26 (3): 520-28.
  • Fisher, R. (1958), The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection. 2nd ed. Dover Publications.
  • Gould, S. J., y R. C. Lewontin (1979), “The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme,” Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Biological Sciences 205 (1161): 581-98.
  • Griffiths, P. E. (1996), “Darwinism, process structuralism, and natural kinds,” Philosophy of Science 63 (5): 1-9.
  • Kirschner, M., y J. Gerhart (1998), “Evolvability,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 95 (15): 8420-27.
  • Lenski, Richard E., Jeffrey E. Barrick, y Charles Ofria (2006), “Balancing robustness and evolvability,” PLoS Biology 4 (12): 2190-92. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0040428.
  • Lewontin, R. C. (1974), The Genetic Basis of Evolutionary Change. Columbia Biological Series. New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Maynard-Smith, J., R. Burian, S. Kauffman, P. Alberch, J. Campbell, B. Goodwin, R. Lande, D. Raup, y L. Wolpert (1985), “Developmental constraints and evolution: a perspective from the Mountain Lake Conference on Development and Evolution,” The Quarterly Review of Biology 60 (3): 265.
  • Mayr, E.) (1961), “Cause and effect in biology: Kinds of causes, predictability, and teleology are viewed by a practicing biologist,” Science 134 (3489): 1501-6. — (1978), “La evolución,” Investigación y Ciencia 26: 6-16.
  • Merlin, F. (2010), “Evolutionary chance mutation: a defense of the Modern Synthesis’ consensus view,” Info: Ann Arbor, MI: M Publishing, University of Michigan Library 2.
  • Millstein, R.L. (2016), “Probability in biology: the case of fitness,” en The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy, editado por A. Hájek, y C. Hitchcock. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Monod, J. (1986), El azar y la necesidad (Ensayo sobre la filosofía natural de la biología moderna), Traducido por Ferrer Lerin, F. Barcelona: Ediciones Orbis.
  • Müller, G. B. (2006), “Six memos for evo-devo,” en From Embryology to Evo-devo: a History of Developmental Evolution, editado por J. Maienschein y M. D. Laubichler, 499-524. Cambridge: MIT Press.
  • — (2010), “Epigenetic innovation,” en Evolution: the Extended Syntheses, editado por M. Pigliucci y G. B Müller, MIT Press, 308-32. Cambridge.
  • Newmann, S., y Müller (2006), “Genes and form. Inherency in the evolution of developmental mechanisms,” en Genes in Development: Re-Reading the Molecular Paradigm, editado por E. M. Neumann-Held y C. Rehmann-Sutter, 38-73. Duke University Press.
  • Nuño de la Rosa, L. (2014), “On the possible, the conceivable, and the actual in evolutionary theory,” Biological Theory, 1-8. doi:10.1007/s13752-014-0173-z.
  • Orr, H. A. (2000.),“Adaptation and the cost of complexity,” Evolution; International Journal of Organic Evolution 54 (1): 13-20.
  • Oster, G., y P. Alberch (1982), “Evolution and bifurcation of developmental programs,” Evolution, 36 (3): 444-59.
  • Pigliucci, M. (2008), “Is evolvability evolvable?” Nature Reviews. Genetics 9 (1): 75-82.
  • Pigliucci, M., y G. B. Müller (2010), Evolution, the Extended Synthesis. MIT Press.
  • Raup, D. M. (1966), “Geometric analysis of shell coiling: general problems,” Journal of Paleontology 182: 1178-90.
  • Richardson, M. K., y A. D. Chipman (2003), “Developmental constraints in a comparative framework: a test case using variations in phalanx number during amniote evolution,” Journal of Experimental Zoology (Mol. Dev. Evol.) 296 (1): 8-22.
  • Riedl, R. (1978), Order in Living Organisms: A Systems Analysis of Evolution. NY: Wiley.
  • Rieppel, O. (1990), “Structuralism, Functionalism, and the four Aristotelian causes,” Journal of the History of Biology 23 (2): 291-320. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4331131.
  • — (2005), “Modules, kinds, and homology,” Journal of Experimental Zoology Part B Molecular and Developmental Evolution 304 (1): 18-27.
  • — (2006), ““Type” in morphology and phylogeny”, Journal of Morphology 267 (5): 528-35.
  • Salazar-Ciudad, I. (2006), “Developmental constraints vs. variational properties: how pattern formation can help to understand evolution and development,” Journal of Experimental Zoology Part B: Molecular and Developmental Evolution 306B (2): 107-25.
  • Salazar-Ciudad, I., y J. Jernvall (2004), “How different types of pattern formation mechanisms affect the evolution of form and development,” Evolution & Development 6 (1): 6-16.
  • Schwenk, K. (1995), “A utilitarian approach to evolutionary constraint,” Zoology. http://hydrodictyon.eeb.uconn.edu/people/schwenk/SchwenkConstraint95 .pdf.
  • Sterelny, K. (2000), “Development, evolution, and adaptation,” Philosophy of Science, 67 (1): 369-87. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/188681.
  • Von Dassow, G., E. Meir, E. M. Munro, y G. M. Odell (2000), “The segment polarity network is a robust developmental module,” Nature 406 (6792): 188-92.
  • Von Dassow, G., y E. Munro (1999), “Modularity in animal development and evolution: Elements of a conceptual framework for Evo-Devo,” Journal of Experimental Zoology 285 (4): 307-25.
  • Wagner, G. P. (1989), “The biological homology concept,” Ann. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 20 (1): 51-69.
  • — (1996), “Homologues, natural kinds and the evolution of modularity,” American Zoologist 36 (1): 36-43.
  • — (2014), Homology, Genes, and Evolutionary Innovation. Princeton University Press. https://books.google.com/books?id=g7vzAgAAQBAJ&pgis=1.
  • Wagner, G. P., y L. Altenberg (1996), “Perspective: complex adaptations and the evolution of evolvability,” Evolution 50 (3): 967-76.
  • Wagner, G. P., y M. D. Laubichler (2004), “Rupert Riedl and the re-synthesis of evolutionary and developmental biology: body plans and evolvability,” Journal of Experimental Zoology (Mol Dev Evol) 302: 92-102.
  • Wagner, G. P., y B. Y Misof (1993), “How can a character be developmentally constrained despite variation in developmental pathways?” Journal of Evolutionary Biology 6 (3): 449-55.
  • Wagner, G. P., y G. P. Wagner (2001), “Characters, units and natural kinds: an introduction,” en The Character Concept in Evolutionary Biology, G. P. Wagner (ed.), NY: Academic Press, 1-10.